what you think of the doctrine.  Does it make sense?  Or is it problematic in some way?

Human Anatomy & Physiology (11th Edition)
11th Edition
ISBN:9780134580999
Author:Elaine N. Marieb, Katja N. Hoehn
Publisher:Elaine N. Marieb, Katja N. Hoehn
Chapter1: The Human Body: An Orientation
Section: Chapter Questions
Problem 1RQ: The correct sequence of levels forming the structural hierarchy is A. (a) organ, organ system,...
icon
Related questions
Question

what you think of the doctrine.  Does it make sense?  Or is it problematic in some way?  

2/ Foot /"The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect"
cave. Luckily (luckily?) the trapped party have with them
a stick of dynamite with which they can blast the fat man
out of the mouth of the cave. Either they use the dynamite
or they drown. In one version the fat man, whose head is
in the cave, will drown with them; in the other he will be
rescued in due course. Problem: may they use the
dynamite or not? Later we shall find parallels to this
example. Here it is introduced for light relief and because
it will serve to show how ridiculous one version of the
depends, and that it seemed to yield one sophistical
conclusion when applied to the problem of abortion. The
reason for its appeal is that its opponents have often
seemed to be committed to quite indefensible views. Thus
the controversy has raged around examples such as the
following. Suppose that a judge or magistrate is faced
with rioters demanding that a culprit be found for a
certain crime and threatening otherwise to take their own
bloody revenge on a particular section of the community.
The real culprit being unknown, the judge sees himself as
able to prevent the bloodshed only by framing some
innocent person and having him executed. Beside this
example is placed another in which a pilot whose airplane
is about to crash is deciding whether to steer from a more
to a less inhabited area. To make the parallel as close as
possible it may rather be supposed that he is the driver of
a runaway tram which he can only steer from one narrow
track on to another; five men are working on one track
and one man on the other; anyone on the track he enters is
bound to be killed. In the case of the riots the mob have
five hostages, so that in both the exchange is supposed to
be one man's life for the lives of five. The question is
why we should say, without hesitation, that the driver
should steer for the less occupied track, while most of us
would be appalled at the idea that the innocent man could
be framed. It may be suggested that the special feature of
the latter case is that it involves the corruption of justice,
and this is, of course, very important indeed. But if we
remove that special feature, supposing that some private
individual is to kill an innocent person and pass him offas
the criminal we still find ourselves horrified by the idea.
The doctrine of double effect offers us a way out of the
difficulty, insisting that it is one thing to steer towards
someone foreseeing that you will kill him and another to
aim at his death as part of your plan. Moreover there is
one very important element of good in what is here
insisted. In real life it would hardly ever be certain that
the man on the narrow track would be killed. Perhaps he
might find a foothold on the side of the tunnel and cling
on as the vehicle hurtled by. The driver of the tram does
not then leap off and brain him with a crowbar. The
judge, however, needs the death of the innocent man for
his (good) purposes. If the victim proves hard to hang he
must see to it that he dies another way. To choose to
execute him is to choose that this evil shall come about,
and this must therefore count as a certainty in weighing
up the good and evil involved. The distinction between
direct and oblique intention is crucial here, and is of great
importance in an uncertain world. Nevertheless this is no
way to defend the doctrine of double effect. For the
question is whether the difference between aiming at
something and obliquely intending it is in itself relevant to
moral decisions; not whether it is important when
correlated with a difference of certainty in the balance of
good and evil. Moreover we are particularly interested in
the application of the doctrine of the double effect to the
question of abortion, and no one can deny that in
doctrine of the double effect would be. For suppose that
the trapped explorers were to argue that the death of the
fat man might be taken as a merely foreseen consequence
of the act of blowing him up. ("We didn't want to kill him
... only to blow him into small pieces" or even ".. only
to blast him out of the cave.") I believe that those who use
the doctrine of the double effect would rightly reject such
a suggestion, though they will, of course, have
considerable difficulty in explaining where the line is to
be drawn. What is to be the criterion of "claseness" if we
say that anything very close to what we are literally
aiming at counts as if part of our aim?
Let us leave this difficulty aside and return to the
arguments for and against the doctrine, supposing it to be
formulated in the way considered most effective by its
supporters, and ourselves bypassing the trouble by taking
what must on any reasonable definition be clear cases of
"direct" or "oblique" intention.
The first point that should be made clear, in fairness to the
theory, is that no one is suggesting that it does not matter
what you bring about as long as you merely foresee and
do not strictly intend the evil that follows. We might
think, for instance, of the (actual) case of wicked
merchants selling, for cooking, oil they knew to be
poisonous and thereby killing a number of innocent
people, comparing and contrasting it with that of some
unemployed gravediggers, desperate for custom, who got
hold of this same oil and sold it (or perhaps they secretly
gave it away) in order to create orders for graves. They
strictly (directly) intend the deaths they cause, while the
merchants could say that it was not part of their plan that
anyone should die. In morality, as in law, the merchants,
like the gravediggers, would be considered as murderers;
nor are the supporters of the doctrine of the double effect
bound to say that there is the least difference between
them in respect of moral turpitude. What they are
committed to is the thesis that sometimes it makes a
difference to the permissibility of an action involving
harm to others that this harm, although foreseen, is not
part of the agent's direct intention. An end such as
carning one's living is clearly not such as to justify either
the direct or oblique intention of the death of innocent
people, but in certain cases one is justified in bringing
about knowingly what one could not directly intend.
It is now time to say why this doctrine should be taken
seriously in spite of the fact that it sounds rather odd, that
there are difficulties about the distinction on which it
Transcribed Image Text:2/ Foot /"The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect" cave. Luckily (luckily?) the trapped party have with them a stick of dynamite with which they can blast the fat man out of the mouth of the cave. Either they use the dynamite or they drown. In one version the fat man, whose head is in the cave, will drown with them; in the other he will be rescued in due course. Problem: may they use the dynamite or not? Later we shall find parallels to this example. Here it is introduced for light relief and because it will serve to show how ridiculous one version of the depends, and that it seemed to yield one sophistical conclusion when applied to the problem of abortion. The reason for its appeal is that its opponents have often seemed to be committed to quite indefensible views. Thus the controversy has raged around examples such as the following. Suppose that a judge or magistrate is faced with rioters demanding that a culprit be found for a certain crime and threatening otherwise to take their own bloody revenge on a particular section of the community. The real culprit being unknown, the judge sees himself as able to prevent the bloodshed only by framing some innocent person and having him executed. Beside this example is placed another in which a pilot whose airplane is about to crash is deciding whether to steer from a more to a less inhabited area. To make the parallel as close as possible it may rather be supposed that he is the driver of a runaway tram which he can only steer from one narrow track on to another; five men are working on one track and one man on the other; anyone on the track he enters is bound to be killed. In the case of the riots the mob have five hostages, so that in both the exchange is supposed to be one man's life for the lives of five. The question is why we should say, without hesitation, that the driver should steer for the less occupied track, while most of us would be appalled at the idea that the innocent man could be framed. It may be suggested that the special feature of the latter case is that it involves the corruption of justice, and this is, of course, very important indeed. But if we remove that special feature, supposing that some private individual is to kill an innocent person and pass him offas the criminal we still find ourselves horrified by the idea. The doctrine of double effect offers us a way out of the difficulty, insisting that it is one thing to steer towards someone foreseeing that you will kill him and another to aim at his death as part of your plan. Moreover there is one very important element of good in what is here insisted. In real life it would hardly ever be certain that the man on the narrow track would be killed. Perhaps he might find a foothold on the side of the tunnel and cling on as the vehicle hurtled by. The driver of the tram does not then leap off and brain him with a crowbar. The judge, however, needs the death of the innocent man for his (good) purposes. If the victim proves hard to hang he must see to it that he dies another way. To choose to execute him is to choose that this evil shall come about, and this must therefore count as a certainty in weighing up the good and evil involved. The distinction between direct and oblique intention is crucial here, and is of great importance in an uncertain world. Nevertheless this is no way to defend the doctrine of double effect. For the question is whether the difference between aiming at something and obliquely intending it is in itself relevant to moral decisions; not whether it is important when correlated with a difference of certainty in the balance of good and evil. Moreover we are particularly interested in the application of the doctrine of the double effect to the question of abortion, and no one can deny that in doctrine of the double effect would be. For suppose that the trapped explorers were to argue that the death of the fat man might be taken as a merely foreseen consequence of the act of blowing him up. ("We didn't want to kill him ... only to blow him into small pieces" or even ".. only to blast him out of the cave.") I believe that those who use the doctrine of the double effect would rightly reject such a suggestion, though they will, of course, have considerable difficulty in explaining where the line is to be drawn. What is to be the criterion of "claseness" if we say that anything very close to what we are literally aiming at counts as if part of our aim? Let us leave this difficulty aside and return to the arguments for and against the doctrine, supposing it to be formulated in the way considered most effective by its supporters, and ourselves bypassing the trouble by taking what must on any reasonable definition be clear cases of "direct" or "oblique" intention. The first point that should be made clear, in fairness to the theory, is that no one is suggesting that it does not matter what you bring about as long as you merely foresee and do not strictly intend the evil that follows. We might think, for instance, of the (actual) case of wicked merchants selling, for cooking, oil they knew to be poisonous and thereby killing a number of innocent people, comparing and contrasting it with that of some unemployed gravediggers, desperate for custom, who got hold of this same oil and sold it (or perhaps they secretly gave it away) in order to create orders for graves. They strictly (directly) intend the deaths they cause, while the merchants could say that it was not part of their plan that anyone should die. In morality, as in law, the merchants, like the gravediggers, would be considered as murderers; nor are the supporters of the doctrine of the double effect bound to say that there is the least difference between them in respect of moral turpitude. What they are committed to is the thesis that sometimes it makes a difference to the permissibility of an action involving harm to others that this harm, although foreseen, is not part of the agent's direct intention. An end such as carning one's living is clearly not such as to justify either the direct or oblique intention of the death of innocent people, but in certain cases one is justified in bringing about knowingly what one could not directly intend. It is now time to say why this doctrine should be taken seriously in spite of the fact that it sounds rather odd, that there are difficulties about the distinction on which it
The Problem of Abortion and the
Doctrine of the Double Effect
contrast a man is said not strictly, or directly, to intend the
foreseen consequences of his voluntary actions where
these are neither the end at which he is aiming nor the
means to this end. Whether the word "intention" should
Philippa Foot
1967. Oxford Review, No. 5. Included in Foot,
1977/2002 lirtues and Vices and Other Essays in
Moral Philosophy. (Minor stylistic amendments have
been made.)
be applied in both cases is not of course what matters:
Bentham spoke of "oblique intention," contrasting it with
the "direct intention" of ends and means, and we may as
well follow his terminology. Everyone must recognize
that some such distinction can be made, though it may be
made in a number of different ways, and it is the
distinction that is crucial to the doctrine of the double
effect. The words "double effect" refer to the two effects
One of the reasons why most of us feel puzzled about the
problem of abortion is that we want, and do not want, to
allow to the unborn child the rights that belong to adults
and children. When we think of a baby about to be born it
that an action may produce: the one aimed at, and the one
foreseen but in no way desired. By "he doctrine of the
double effect" I mean the thesis that it is sometimes
permissible to bring about by oblique intention what one
may not directly intend. Thus the distinction is held to be
relevant to moral decision in certain difficult cases. It is
said for instance that the operation of hysterectomy
involves the death of the fetus as the foreseen but not
seems absurd to think that the next few minutes or even
hours could make so radical a difference to its status; yet
as we go back in the life of the fetus we are more and
more reluctant to say that this is a human being and must
be treated as such. No doubt this is the deepest source of
our dilemma, but it is not the only one. For we are also
confused about the general question of what we may and
may not do where the interests of human beings conflict.
We have strong intuitions about certain cases; saying, for
instance, that it is all right to raise the level of education
in our country, though statistics allow us to predict that a
rise in the suicide rate will follow, while it is not all right
to kill the feeble-minded to aid cancer research. It is not
strictly or directly intended consequence of the surgeon's
act, while other operations kill the child and count as the
direct intention of taking an innocent life, a distinction
that has evoked particularly bitter reactions on the part of
non-Catholics. If you are permitted to bring about the
death of the child, what does it matter how it is done? The
doctrine of the double effect is also used to show why in
another case, where a woman in labor will die unless a
craniotomy operation is performed, the intervention is not
to be condoned. There, it is said, we may not operate but
casy, however, to see the principles involved, and one
way of throwing light on the abortion issue will be by
setting up parallels involving adults or children once born.
So we will be able to isolate the "equal rights" issue and
should be able to make some advance.
must let the mother die. We foresee her death but do not
directly intend it, whereas to crush the skull of the child
would count as direct intention of its death
I shall not, of course, discuss all the principles that may
be used in deciding how to act where the interests or
rights of human beings conflict. What I want to do is to
look at one particular theory, known as the "doctrine of
the double effect" which is invoked by Catholics in
support of their views on abortion but supposed by them
to apply elsewhere. As used in the abortion argument this
doctrine has often seemed to non-Catholics to be a piece
of complete sophistry. In the last number of the Oxford
Review it was given short shrift by Professor Hart' And
yet this principle has seemed to some non-Catholics as
well as to Catholics to stand as the only defence against
decisions on other issues that are quite unacceptable. It
will help us in our difficulty about abortion if this conflict
can be resolved.
This last application of the doctrine has been queried by
Professor Hart on the ground that the child's death is not
strictly a means to saving the mother's life and should
logically be treated as an unwanted
consequence by those who make use of the distinction
between direct and oblique intention. To interpret the
doctrine in this way is perfectly reasonable given the
language that has been used; it would, however, make
nonsense of it from the beginning. A certain event may be
desired under one of its descriptions, unwanted under
another, but we cannot treat these as two different events,
foreseen
one of which is aimed at and the other not. And even if it
be argued that there are here two different events the
crushing of the child's skull and its death-the two are
obviously much too close for an application of the
doctrine of the double effect. To see how odd it would be
to apply the principle like this we may consider the story,
well known to philosophers, of the fat man stuck in the
mouth of the cave. A party of potholers have imprudently
allowed the fat man to lead them as they make their way
out of the cave, and he gets stuck, trapping the others
behind him. Obviously the right thing to do is to sit down
and wait until the fat man grows thin; but philosophers
have arranged that floodwaters should be rising within the
The doctrine of the double effect is based on a distinction
between what a man foresees as a result of his voluntary
action and what, in the strict sense, he intends. He intends
in the strictest sense both those things that he aims at as
ends and those that he aims at as means to his ends. The
latter may be regretted in themselves but nevertheless
desired for the sake of the end, as we may intend to keepP
dangerous lunatics confined for the sake of our safety. By
Transcribed Image Text:The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect contrast a man is said not strictly, or directly, to intend the foreseen consequences of his voluntary actions where these are neither the end at which he is aiming nor the means to this end. Whether the word "intention" should Philippa Foot 1967. Oxford Review, No. 5. Included in Foot, 1977/2002 lirtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. (Minor stylistic amendments have been made.) be applied in both cases is not of course what matters: Bentham spoke of "oblique intention," contrasting it with the "direct intention" of ends and means, and we may as well follow his terminology. Everyone must recognize that some such distinction can be made, though it may be made in a number of different ways, and it is the distinction that is crucial to the doctrine of the double effect. The words "double effect" refer to the two effects One of the reasons why most of us feel puzzled about the problem of abortion is that we want, and do not want, to allow to the unborn child the rights that belong to adults and children. When we think of a baby about to be born it that an action may produce: the one aimed at, and the one foreseen but in no way desired. By "he doctrine of the double effect" I mean the thesis that it is sometimes permissible to bring about by oblique intention what one may not directly intend. Thus the distinction is held to be relevant to moral decision in certain difficult cases. It is said for instance that the operation of hysterectomy involves the death of the fetus as the foreseen but not seems absurd to think that the next few minutes or even hours could make so radical a difference to its status; yet as we go back in the life of the fetus we are more and more reluctant to say that this is a human being and must be treated as such. No doubt this is the deepest source of our dilemma, but it is not the only one. For we are also confused about the general question of what we may and may not do where the interests of human beings conflict. We have strong intuitions about certain cases; saying, for instance, that it is all right to raise the level of education in our country, though statistics allow us to predict that a rise in the suicide rate will follow, while it is not all right to kill the feeble-minded to aid cancer research. It is not strictly or directly intended consequence of the surgeon's act, while other operations kill the child and count as the direct intention of taking an innocent life, a distinction that has evoked particularly bitter reactions on the part of non-Catholics. If you are permitted to bring about the death of the child, what does it matter how it is done? The doctrine of the double effect is also used to show why in another case, where a woman in labor will die unless a craniotomy operation is performed, the intervention is not to be condoned. There, it is said, we may not operate but casy, however, to see the principles involved, and one way of throwing light on the abortion issue will be by setting up parallels involving adults or children once born. So we will be able to isolate the "equal rights" issue and should be able to make some advance. must let the mother die. We foresee her death but do not directly intend it, whereas to crush the skull of the child would count as direct intention of its death I shall not, of course, discuss all the principles that may be used in deciding how to act where the interests or rights of human beings conflict. What I want to do is to look at one particular theory, known as the "doctrine of the double effect" which is invoked by Catholics in support of their views on abortion but supposed by them to apply elsewhere. As used in the abortion argument this doctrine has often seemed to non-Catholics to be a piece of complete sophistry. In the last number of the Oxford Review it was given short shrift by Professor Hart' And yet this principle has seemed to some non-Catholics as well as to Catholics to stand as the only defence against decisions on other issues that are quite unacceptable. It will help us in our difficulty about abortion if this conflict can be resolved. This last application of the doctrine has been queried by Professor Hart on the ground that the child's death is not strictly a means to saving the mother's life and should logically be treated as an unwanted consequence by those who make use of the distinction between direct and oblique intention. To interpret the doctrine in this way is perfectly reasonable given the language that has been used; it would, however, make nonsense of it from the beginning. A certain event may be desired under one of its descriptions, unwanted under another, but we cannot treat these as two different events, foreseen one of which is aimed at and the other not. And even if it be argued that there are here two different events the crushing of the child's skull and its death-the two are obviously much too close for an application of the doctrine of the double effect. To see how odd it would be to apply the principle like this we may consider the story, well known to philosophers, of the fat man stuck in the mouth of the cave. A party of potholers have imprudently allowed the fat man to lead them as they make their way out of the cave, and he gets stuck, trapping the others behind him. Obviously the right thing to do is to sit down and wait until the fat man grows thin; but philosophers have arranged that floodwaters should be rising within the The doctrine of the double effect is based on a distinction between what a man foresees as a result of his voluntary action and what, in the strict sense, he intends. He intends in the strictest sense both those things that he aims at as ends and those that he aims at as means to his ends. The latter may be regretted in themselves but nevertheless desired for the sake of the end, as we may intend to keepP dangerous lunatics confined for the sake of our safety. By
Expert Solution
trending now

Trending now

This is a popular solution!

steps

Step by step

Solved in 2 steps

Blurred answer
Knowledge Booster
Violence
Learn more about
Need a deep-dive on the concept behind this application? Look no further. Learn more about this topic, biology and related others by exploring similar questions and additional content below.
Similar questions
Recommended textbooks for you
Human Anatomy & Physiology (11th Edition)
Human Anatomy & Physiology (11th Edition)
Biology
ISBN:
9780134580999
Author:
Elaine N. Marieb, Katja N. Hoehn
Publisher:
PEARSON
Biology 2e
Biology 2e
Biology
ISBN:
9781947172517
Author:
Matthew Douglas, Jung Choi, Mary Ann Clark
Publisher:
OpenStax
Anatomy & Physiology
Anatomy & Physiology
Biology
ISBN:
9781259398629
Author:
McKinley, Michael P., O'loughlin, Valerie Dean, Bidle, Theresa Stouter
Publisher:
Mcgraw Hill Education,
Molecular Biology of the Cell (Sixth Edition)
Molecular Biology of the Cell (Sixth Edition)
Biology
ISBN:
9780815344322
Author:
Bruce Alberts, Alexander D. Johnson, Julian Lewis, David Morgan, Martin Raff, Keith Roberts, Peter Walter
Publisher:
W. W. Norton & Company
Laboratory Manual For Human Anatomy & Physiology
Laboratory Manual For Human Anatomy & Physiology
Biology
ISBN:
9781260159363
Author:
Martin, Terry R., Prentice-craver, Cynthia
Publisher:
McGraw-Hill Publishing Co.
Inquiry Into Life (16th Edition)
Inquiry Into Life (16th Edition)
Biology
ISBN:
9781260231700
Author:
Sylvia S. Mader, Michael Windelspecht
Publisher:
McGraw Hill Education