Student5.edited (4)

docx

School

County College of Morris *

*We aren’t endorsed by this school

Course

HJ

Subject

Philosophy

Date

Nov 24, 2024

Type

docx

Pages

6

Report

Uploaded by SuperHumanCrown14955

Surname 1 Student’s Name Institution Affiliation Course Date Philosophy of Human Nature- Jesse Prinz’s perspective Prinz arguement for relativism According to Jesse Prinz, morality is merely culturally entrenched. This means that the sources of our moral inclinations are merely cultural, as there is nothing like moral absolutism. The article by Jesse Prinz titled “Morality is a Culturally Conditioned Response” argues in favor of moral relativism and supports the relativism theory of ethics that moral judgments are based on the emotions that stem from social norms and culture (Prinz, p6) . As such, Prinz contends cultural values and beliefs are responsible for personal morality and that morality cannot be said to stem or be inherent in the natural world. Therefore, the article rejects that there is absolute morality but rather accepts that morality is culturally inbound because it discusses how morality has changed throughout time and how different cultures have had different views on morality (Prinz, p6) . This means there is no absolute morality as stated moral values are relative to time and circumstances, and therefore clashing moral beliefs can be true. Prinz is aware of the objectivists, as some may say moral variations is greatly exaggerated. However, he uses what he calls "deny variation matters" to defend his argument on moral relativism. Prinz's argument for morality relativism is described below. Jesse Prinz creates two arguments in support of moral relativism that there is no absolute morality but moral beliefs and practices are merely culturally inclined. The first argument in support of moral relativism is that morals vary dramatically across time and space and that different people have different views on morality (Prinz, p6) . He uses the hypothetical situation in which he talks of the scenario of moral disagreement to introduce the idea of relativism, that moral values are relative to time and circumstances. Here, the hypothetical
2 situation of moral disagreement points out that moral values are not absolute and universal in society but rather ingrained with cultural beliefs and values. He supports the argument with a request to consider cannibalism since, according to evidence, 34% of cultures are stated to have practiced cannibalism (Prinz, p7) . In this view, Prinz highlights how there are inconsistencies between what different groups of people regard as good or evil to support no absolutism morality as there are variations in moral codes across cultures. As such, Prinz brings the concept of variation to show how certain things that are considered evil are good to some cultures. Therefore, he uses the argument on variation to state people do not share moral values (Prinz, p6) . This makes Prinz refute the argument of moral objectivism. Therefore, Prinz’s main argument is that morality is different for everybody; thus, there is no absolute or universal morality, as moral values stem from what an individual believes based on social norms and culture. The second argument raised in support of moral relativism is that moral judgments are based on emotions and hence vary from person to person. The subtitle “Emotions and Inculcation” states ethics is based on emotions rather than reason, as there is a strong link between moral values with emotional attitude and reasoning. Thus, no amount of reasoning can inculcate morals (Prinz, p7) . Prinz uses the example of homosexuals and psychopaths to show they are morally blind because they lack the emotional attitude to tell them their actions are morally wrong. As such, he states that shame and disgust are the definite chief precursors of moral judgment (Prinz, p7) . To explain his argument to support moral relativism and shun moral objectivism, Prinz comes down to the level of the reader, who may not understand the technicalities of philosophy, by giving an example of how a person may feel disgusted by eating cow tongue but would not be ashamed of eating it if not a vegetarian. As a result, the emotion of killing an innocent animal is wrong affects the moral judgment rather than the person using logic and reason. This means that emotions remain the choice of correct moral
3 judgment rather than reasoning. Therefore, moral judgment is based on the emotional attitude of the individuals, as reasoning or logic cannot tell us which facts are morally good or bad because it is evaluatively neutral (Prinz, p7) . The arguments raised by Prinz support moral relativism and work towards explaining that there is no absolute morality but rather based on what the culture and emotional beliefs state of being right or wrong. How Prinz defends his argument against an objection Prinz defends his argument against the objection of moral relativism through critics of what objectivists use as the basis of moral relativism. In what he calls denying variations matters, Prinz states that objectivists say that morality varies across cultures, so according to them, variations do not matter in determining morality (Prinz, p8) . They also say that people share moral values; thus, moral principles are absolute or universal to all cultures, which contradicts moral relativism. This shows Prinz is aware of the objection to his argument on moral relativism to be merely culturally entrenched and thus criticizes objectivists’ views with the analogy of moral theory and scientific theory. How Prinz responds to this objection Prinz responds to objectivists’ view of morality through comparison with scientific theory and the arguments on infanticide. First, Prinz responds to objections to his moral relativism by comparing the differences in morality with the differences in scientific theories. He states that in science, not all theories that tend to explain a phenomenon are true, and similarly, in morality, no basis or moral solutions in the form of theories inherent in the natural world are the right ones (Prinz, p8) . Here, he uses this analogy to support morality being a culturally conditioned response because scientific theories are subject to variation due to time and circumstances. This is similar to moral theories because cultures tend to evolve with time; thus no absolutism of morality. The article shows there is no correct scientific theory. Thus, variations in scientific theory arise due to inadequate observations, poor instruments, and
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help
4 research (Prinz, p8) . Similarly, in moral theory, there is no correct morality that can be defined as doing good or bad varies from person to person. This analogy shows that morality cannot be quantified as no measure of what is good or wrong, so it cannot be a basis for defining what morality is. Here, Prinz uses the piercing argument of slavery and how it was perpetuated despite improvement in science to support that the advances of scientific observations over time did not affect how we view morality (Prinz, p8) . Therefore, we can only base moral values based on what people culturally believe and not through mere reasoning that there is a common way for all people to show moral values. Objectivists state that people share moral values, but circumstances that people are in bring about variations in determining what is right or wrong. As such, moral variations stated by Prinz are greatly exaggerated (Prinz, p7) . According to Prinz, objectivists' reasoning is clumsy and, as a result, use the case of infanticide to respond to this objection. He states that if people share moral values and variations are exaggerated, why should we believe that Inuits practiced infanticide as the right solution to resource scarcity in the tundra (Prinz, p7) ? This shows that we cannot justify infanticide used by Inuits in moral reasoning but due to logical reasoning. As such, we cannot share moral values and justify the Inuit's practice of infanticide since moral values vary from person to person (Prinz, p7) . These differences in how we can arrive at moral judgment make Prinz criticize the common arguments posed in objectivists' morality arguments. Are you convinced by Prinz's response to this objection? In my opinion, I think Prinz successfully expressed his response to objection and refuted the objectivist’s theory and views on his morality relativism. Therefore, I am convinced with his response to objections because Prinz's arguments against what is stated in denying variations matters have a strong appeal to the reader's logic. Prinz refutes the objections to his moral stance on cultural values through the analogy of moral theory and scientific theories
5 (Prinz, p9) . He creatively and critically states that as scientific theories are subject to change over time and place, moral values are also subject to change from one person to another. This is also the subject of how cultures evolve because people tend to inbound their moral values with their cultures since emotions that define morality are culturally entrenched. This comparison makes the reader appeal to logic that there is no absolutism morality. This example of how Prinz responds to objectivists' view of morality relativism shows that Prinz addresses the objection head-on and explains them fully for the reader to understand and appeal to logic (Prinz, p6) . He then refutes the allegations from the objectivists with strong counter-arguments that have a logical sense to make the reader able to understand the reasoning he uses on the objections raised. He has used ethos commendably and appropriately to strengthen his own arguments against objections that create a rational connection to the reader's mind. Therefore, I think Prinz has praiseworthy deductive reasoning skills that make the reader able to see how he creatively responded to the objection. As such, I am convinced by the responses that he postulates in defense of his moral relativism and counter-arguments to the objections.
6 Works Cited Prinz, Jesse. "Morality is a culturally conditioned response." Philosophy Now 82 (2011): 6-9. philosophynow.org/issues/82/Morality_is_a_Culturally_Conditioned_Response.
Your preview ends here
Eager to read complete document? Join bartleby learn and gain access to the full version
  • Access to all documents
  • Unlimited textbook solutions
  • 24/7 expert homework help